African American Pragmatism: A Review Essay

 

J. Kameron Carter

 

            Previously a dissertation fellow at the Institute for Advanced Studies in Culture, J. Kameron Carter is currently Assistant Professor of Theology and Black Church Studies at Duke University, The Divinity School. His first book, Race: A Theological Account, is forthcoming from Oxford University Press.

 

            Harris, Leonard. The Critical Pragmatism of Alain Locke: A Reader on Value Theory, Aesthetics, Community, Culture, Race, and Education. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 1999.

            Wood, Mark David. Cornel West and the Politics of Prophetic Pragmatism. Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 2000.

            "Alain Locke was a pragmatist." So begins Leonard Harris' book The Critical Pragmatism of Alain Locke: A Reader on Value Theory, Aesthetics, Community, Culture, Race, and Education, an important collection of essays that assesses Locke's thought, evaluating his relationship to modern philosophy—American pragmatism, in particular—in light of the questions he raised about value, identity, pluralism, multiculturalism, and education. If the value of a collection of this sort is whether the essays stimulate readers to a fresh appraisal of and engagement with, its central figure, then certainly Harris' editorial labors have not been in vain. With this collection of critical essays, Harris, a philosopher and well-respected Locke scholar in his own right, provides a complement to his previously published anthology, The Philosophy of Alain Locke, a collection of primary texts expressing Locke's philosophy and its pragmatist bent. Ranging over a broad field of topics and disciplines, The Critical Pragmatism of Alain Locke brings together essays from a number of scholars to assess and recommend Locke's critically pragmatic orientation. That orientation offered, first, a cultural, or non-property-based, analysis of race, what Locke calls "secondary race consciousness" and "social race." However, that orientation offered, second, a class- or property-based analysis of race as well. That is, it offered an analysis that understood the notion of race as emerging from the exigencies of political economy and its history, both domestically and internationally. These two dimensions of Locke's analysis of race together constitute his critical pragmatism.

            Locke's critical pragmatism prefigures in telling ways Cornel West's prophetic pragmatism. In his Cornel West and the Politics of Prophetic Pragmatism, Mark David Wood objects to West's prophetic pragmatism, and in so doing, he may also be read as objecting to a Lockean critical pragmatism as well. Pragmatism, so Wood contends, in its present forms is but a species of an inert postmodernism, which is at the base of a fair bit of recent progressivist politics. As a tool within contemporary cultural and progressivist politics, pragmatism fails to offer a "political theory that supports the work of democratizing global productive and consumptive relations" (6). The constructive task of Wood's work is to proffer just such a theory—one that is rooted in West himself, albeit not West the prophetic pragmatist and promoter of reformist politics (the later West), but rather West the democratic Marxist who promotes a class-based revolutionary politics, which draws on the resources of Christianity (the early West).

The Critical Pragmatism of Alain Locke

 

            Leonard Harris argues that a Lockean critical pragmatism "avoids the pitfalls of critical theory, anticipates its tremendous contribution to human liberation, finds a middle ground between objectivism and subjectivism, and offers an alternative to the limitations of classical pragmatism" (xiii). That is to say, a Lockean critical pragmatism can do what critical theories of varying sorts—be they post-Marxist, legal, race, or gender theories—have been, to the present moment, unable to do. Despite the contribution such theories have made in placing under suspicion established philosophies by destabilizing the subject, shaking epistemological certitude, localizing universal reason, subjectivizing objective truth, weakening strong ontologies—in short, unsettling philosophy, as it is now fashionable to say, as a metaphysical enterprise—they yet remain seriously wanting. Harris' qualm, as he explains in the preface, with the current fashions of critical theory is their inability to offer a positive vision of the human community, one that offers substantive guidance in the face of the hard realities of life and the density of existence. This inability suggests how those theories, in fact, remain beholden at crucial junctures to the established philosophies they would deconstruct. The claim uniting the varied essays of The Critical Pragmatism of Alain Locke, which commends a Lockean critical pragmatism as a diagnostic of the present moment, is that the deconstructionist effort as exemplified in much of postmodern and critical theory may be finally but a moment within modernity itself and its established philosophies. This is a daring, audacious, and important claim, to be sure, one that, as true as it may be, requires further elucidation.

            Such an elucidation, however, is not the purpose of this fine collection. Its purpose is to recommend Locke's thought and his particular deployment of American pragmatism as a resource for getting beyond the stalemates afflicting critical and postmodern theory. Locke's critical pragmatism suggests a politics, a vision of the social order, that gets us somewhere. It offers a narrative of communal identity that can provide direction for "a radically different future." The essays making it up are intent on pointing the way to such a future, through varied considerations of Locke, by offering a narrative of pragmatism that exceeds the logic of modernity. A Lockean critical pragmatism, so the underlying claim of this collection seems to be, can account for the historic limitations of American pragmatism while yet being able to narrate that pragmatism out of the doldrums, indeed the conundrums, of the metanarratives of modernity. I will discuss two aspects of Locke's critical pragmatism here: his pragmatist aesthetics and his pragmatist analysis of race.

            In his essay explaining the "roots and radicalism" of Locke's "pragmatist aesthetics," Richard Shusterman argues that Locke advocated an aesthetic sensibility that was "an intellectual response to the problems one faces in the project of living" (97). In this Locke was a pragmatist clearly in the tradition of Emerson, James, and Dewey. The problems of living are informed by a number of factors, which Shusterman lucidly discusses. I will mention just a few to make clear the critical moment in Locke's "pragmatist aesthetics," and to begin to suggest its limits.

            Locke builds on the Deweyan principle that art is naturalistic, that is, that "the rhythms of the human organism interacting with [the] world" inform art (98). Here we see the artistic value of the Negro spirituals, for example. The spirituals proceed from a bond black folks have maintained with nature. In the aesthetic energies of European culture, claimed Locke and so explains Shusterman, the bond uniting peoples and cultures with nature flickers on the brink of extinction. But the embers may be aesthetically flamed afresh, the bond retrieved, and thus culture revitalized. But its retrieval must necessarily pass through those who have not forsaken the bond, namely, New World black folks. The sign of the bond's eclipse in European culture, explains Shusterman summarizing a passage from The New Negro, a programmatic text of the Harlem Renaissance edited by Locke, is the European technologizing and manipulation of art, "where art worked merely from its own past models while forgetting nature" (98). In short, in European culture art is converted into a mode of power for the manipulation, control, and subjugation of nature and its constituent elements.

            The art of black folks, as exemplified in the Negro spirituals and in the productions of the Harlem Renaissance, reveals a cultural sensibility that maintained the earthy bond between people and culture with nature. Considering this bond through the Negro spirituals reveals that naturalism is not hostile to spirituality or religious seriousness. Actually, it would stand to reason that the bond properly understood is spiritual and religious as such. Religious seriousness and spirituality, understood within a Lockean aesthetic understanding, are an inflection of the fundamental bond between nature and the living creature, a bond that is made and re-made given changes in and through historical conditions and circumstances.

            Here we come to another significant feature of Locke's pragmatism and pragmatic aesthetics, namely, the significance of history and the interactions in and constituting history. This feature of Locke's aesthetics would seem to place priority on particularity as the only avenue through which to judge an aesthetic production. This must be the way, through concreteness and particularity, to consider the value of the spirituals as an expression of the religious consciousness and as an inflection of the bond uniting a people and a culture with nature. In principle, then, Locke's aesthetics would not be grounded in the autonomous subject nor in the grand apparati of universal reason.

            But is this the case in fact? For, curiously (at least from what can be gleaned from Shusterman's essay, which seems to be fairly consistent with the other essays in the collection) Locke bypasses the spirituals' particularity in his evaluation of what aesthetically commends them. The spirituals are thoroughly contained within nature's immanence. But would not a concrete engagement with the spirituals uncover an aesthetic vision in which nature's intelligibility is connected to the transcendent? And might this suggest a communal and socio-political vision grounded in the sheer fecundity of existence, such that the ground of being is sheer gratuity, that is, in Christian terms, caritas? It is, arguably, this dynamic of nature that the spirituals express. It is a vision of the freedom of black existence and even of the cosmos as having a transcendent depth that is immanently visible. A number of the spirituals give voice to this. Approached from this vantage—the vantage, shall I say, of "pragmatic particularity"—the spirituals are not unlike religious chants or icons, whose aesthetic conditions of possibility lie in their being a response to having been creatively and gratuitously called forth by God. The concreteness of the religious traditions, particularly the Christian traditions, is crucial to a critical pragmatic commendation of the aesthetics of the spirituals, yet this possibility is not entertained by Locke, nor is it raised as a question in Shusterman's exposition of him. Locke's pragmatist aesthetics also eschews "the aesthetics of purist segregation or isolation," preferring "the mix" of an "interactive brewing of diversity" (99-100). Both the Negro spirituals and the Harlem Renaissance exemplify "the mix" insofar as they both are the product of certain historical exigencies that have brought into convergence African and European elements, both of which themselves are not homogenous. Art, thus, is culturally "democratic" in form, and in this it advances a radically "democratic" political practice, given that "art is a practical, purposive form of activity" (101).

            Here is a moment of potential convergence between a cultural and political aesthetics, mediated through a pragmatic approach to the problems of life. The possible convergence becomes clearer on considering Locke's New Negro aesthetic. Locke's vision of the New Negro, which highlighted the cultural uniquenesses of black folks, far from advancing a racial purism, understood the mix constitutive of African American culture as contributing to the flowering manifold of American civilization as such (104). In this can be seen the strategic functions to which Locke put the concept of race in aesthetics. His "prime goal [was]…to improve and develop the Negro's artistic creation and thereby also enrich American aesthetics and the world's" (106). Negro art so understood is a philosophical tool that is both cultural and political, a tool to be used in the project of living. By "political" here it is meant that aesthetics tends towards a certain "democratic" social arrangement that is in fact liberating.

            But what might such a "democratic" social arrangement as promoted by a Lockean pragmatic aesthetics look like? Though suggestive of a politics that might "benefit human life" (107), Locke's aesthetics does not seem to mandate one, or any particular one, as preferable over another. If there is any such mandate entailed by Locke's pragmatic aesthetics, it is hidden. In this, a cultural and political aesthetics remain dialectically related, with the former having the final word over the latter. Thus, the true value Shusterman derives from Locke's aesthetics is in how it transcends the conservatism of Deweyan "high culture" or elitist aesthetic sensibilities. Locke's aesthetics in theory embraces the aesthetic value even of popular art (108), something Deweyan aesthetics resisted. This, however, is not to establish that a critical pragmatic aesthetics, which ostensibly unites the cultural and the political, provides a vision of and guidance for the social order. In short, a critical pragmatic aesthetics leaves us with the discourse of cultural difference and incommensurable otherness, and here we arrive at the horizon, the upper limit, of Lockean aesthetics: a political aesthetics finally gets absorbed by a cultural one.

            Nancy Fraser's important essay, "Another Pragmatism: Alain Locke, Critical 'Race' Theory, and the Politics of Culture," theorizes this horizon while uncovering Locke's philosophical foresight on a number of issues. Indeed, one might read her essay as both the alpha and omega of the collection. Fraser includes Locke in the echelon of American pragmatists and attempts to re-narrate American pragmatism, to offer "another pragmatism," through him. His pragmatism puts pragmatism as such to the "test" by employing "social intelligence to guide social practice" on what Du Bois famously called the twentieth century's perennial problem, the "problem of the color line." Locke attended the problem not simply as aesthetician qua black cultural theorist and even black nationalist. According to Fraser, this is the way Locke is typically received. But just as there is "another pragmatism," so there is, one might say, "another Locke": Locke the "critical theorist of society, specifically of the history and political economy of racism…a thinker who is grappling with the tangled relations between culture, political economy, and 'race'" (3). As a result of Fraser's efforts, the Locke who emerges is a pragmatic philosopher whose cultural endeavors rest on a most insightful critique and vision of political economy. Locke the pragmatic philosopher and social theorist reconciles the seeming antinomies of how to weight the political and cultural dimensions in the modern construction of race. This other Locke, the pragmatist philosopher, does not leave aside Locke the aesthetician. Rather, cultural aesthetician and political and social theorist are united as pragmatist philosopher and analyst of race.

            Locke, as Fraser explains, offers an analysis of race that highlights the notion of "power." Insofar as Locke does this he may be read as prefiguring Cornel West's prophetic pragmatism in many ways. For both bring attention to the significant place of political economy, which any thorough account of race in the modern world demands. Locke, in particular, organizes race into three tiers: theoretical, practical, and social. As Fraser explains:

The first, "theoretical" tier comprises biological and physical interpretations of race. The second, "practical" tier comprehends a political-economic interpretation of race as a construct of imperialist domination. The third, "social" tier encompasses modern forms of solidarity that could in principle be decoupled from domination. (7)    He demystifies "theoretical race," showing it to be grounded in questionable science. He notes that race so understood is "static, purity-obsessed, [and] biological" (9). Theoretical race is thoroughly untenable insofar as it neglects history and "misses the dynamic development of human culture and even human biology" (8). When does the idea of theoretical race arise, and do the problems with theoretical race render the notion of race utterly useless? Answering the first part of the question, Locke offers "a political-economic genealogy" of "practical race." "The move," claims Fraser, "is quintessentially pragmatist" in that it moves the discussion from theory to practice (9-10).

            For Locke, imperialism is the engine driving practical race. Locke brilliantly saw early on that the modern construction of race could not be dislodged from modern colonial and imperialist practices. In his consideration of race as a practical construct, Locke saw a connection between the intra-national racial disorder of American slavery and Jim Crowism, on the one hand, and the international economic system of competitive commerce, on the other. Locke argued that America's caste-less society generated "status anxiety, [and] hence a longing for fixed division and boundaries, a longing that Jim Crow arrangements seem[ed] to satisfy" (11). Biologically speaking, then, race is fictive; practically speaking, however, it is non-fictive. If there is to be an overthrow of how race functions in the modern world, it will of necessity be practical. But any practical overthrow requires the overthrow of imperialism or the international economic system of competitive commerce. This in theory would require the implementation of a liberatively different socio-political arrangement that refigures the modern notion of race by undoing the notion of power and domination that underwrites modern racial discourse.

            It is important to understand Locke's placement of religion in the midst of all this. Locke sees its operation here at the site of practice. Fraser does not say much on this score except that Western religion, particularly Christianity, through its missionary endeavors, functioned to "rationalize" imperialism's "commercial imperatives" (10). Thus, Locke, even in criticizing theoretical race by revealing it to be an imperialist practice of domination, depicts religion as theoretically non-descript and, at best, only a "regulative idea" useful for guiding practice towards the fulfillment of the teleological ends of nature for the species, ends themselves that are never really attainable due to the presence of radical evil in both soul and society. At the ground of all of this is the Kantian verdict that religion, or more specifically God, is practically "thinkable" but theoretically "un-cognizable" or empty and non-particular.

            Fraser, thus, perhaps unintentionally helps us understand why Locke's aesthetics is unable to cognize the content of Negro spirituals and why the Christian specificity of a number of the spirituals is in fact significant for a pragmatic conception of blackness. Locke brilliantly saw near the turn of the twentieth century what has only recently caught the attention of a number of contemporary theorists at twentieth century's twilight and this millennium's dawning. He saw that there is a certain Cartesian, but even more, a certain Kantian configuration to modern racial reasoning. Yet, this apex of Locke's philosophic insight is also the nadir of his thought. Locke follows the itinerary of Kantian religion in bracketing the content of the spirituals, and in so doing follows the itinerary of a Kantian construction of race through his pragmatist aesthetics. 1

Cornel West and the Politics of Prophetic Pragmatism

 

            Mark David Wood's Cornel West and the Politics of Prophetic Pragmatism, though rich on a number of levels, yields its greatest fruits perhaps in its responses to the following three questions: What distinguishes the later from the early Cornel West? What is continuous between the early and later West? What is Wood's own "pragmatic" proposal for building upon but, in the end, going beyond West's prophetic pragmatism? The last question is crucial, for West's work is but the occasion, albeit a most important one, for Wood to work out what might be read as a more rigorous pragmatism, one that in fact attempts to retrieve West's crucially important work by dislodging and even redefining the prophetic (read: politically revolutionary) from the pragmatic (read: cultural) West. Wood positions West as having a conflicted and, indeed, incommensurable account of overcoming what politically and culturally ails and afflicts the modern world. Wood shows how the political imperative informing West's prophetic pragmatism is finally compromised because it really does not attend to the concrete realities of how capital creates certain class and racial relations to sustain it. Wood's own proposal for more truly attending to the concrete realities of existence signals a more basic and deeply "pragmatic" trend occurring in African American religious scholarship, a trend that retains some of the problems of pragmatism.

            Central to Wood's critique is accounting for the hiatus between the West of the works coming before and the West of the works coming after the 1989 publication of The American Evasion of Philosophy, where the program of prophetic pragmatism is first clearly articulated in a sustained manner. Wood calls the former the "pre-Evasion" works and describes the hiatus within West's work as follows:

Whereas the aim of West's [pre-Evasion] African American revolutionary Christianity was to build a socio-economic system based on "collective control of major institutions," the aim of his [post-Evasion] prophetic pragmatism is to "revitalize our republic" and "democratize the market economy." The goal is no longer to develop "a revolutionary praxis beyond capitalist civilization" but rather to improve conditions of labor, leisure, and life within the limits of capitalist property relations. (90)     The failure of the later prophetically pragmatic West, so Wood sees it, is in his seeking to democratize market capitalism from within, a democratization that highlights a pragmatic and multicultural pluralism. The salvageability of capitalism is crucial to the outlook of the post-Evasion West.

            There are several moves that West makes to arrive at the conclusion driving prophetic pragmatism, namely, that free market capitalism is salvageable, that it can be redeemed. What appears to be most crucial, at least for Wood, is the influence of Michel Foucault's interpretation of power. This influence is most evident in the post-Evasion works, though minimally present in the pre-Evasion writings as well, indicating problems haranguing West's work at its inception.

            The post-Evasion writings jettison a Marxist understanding of power for the starkly different one grounded in the work of Foucault. Marx saw power as grounded in structures of material class relations. Foucault saw the matter otherwise, indeed, in a poststructuralist fashion. Quoting Power/Knowledge, Wood observes that for Foucault power "passes through much finer channels" than a Marxist notion, which contends that one class has it, while another does not. As Foucault says, "Power must be analyzed as something which circulates, or rather as something which only functions in the form of a chain. It is never localized as here or there…because there is always in each of us something that fights something else" (60-61). Wood concludes from this that "Foucault's theory of power loses its capacity to explain who uses power against whom and for what" (61). A Foucaultian notion of power, then, is non-materialist and, in this, claims Wood, it is metaphysical:

Foucault's concept of power shares more in common with pantheological formulations of divinity than it does with sociological formulations of power that understand power as deriving from an individual's or group of individuals' possession of some natural resource (e.g., an oil field, forest, or uranium deposit) or machine (e.g., a tractor, refinery, missile) and the authority and ability to use them to realize determinant goals. (61)             This stands in stark contrast with the work of the pre-Evasion West and his advance of an African American radical or revolutionary Christianity, which seeks to abolish the socio-economic realities that generate racial inequalities in the first place. For the early West, as for Locke, this means the abolishment of capital and the property relations attending it:

The exploitation of labor, the investment goal of profit maximization, and global capitalist competition are the principal forces responsible for the regeneration of racialized occupational segregation and the resulting average income and wealth inequalities between and within groups of persons designated "white" and "black." (74)            Wood sees West as correct in his fundamental intuition on the matter. The racial naming of groups as white, black, and so on is the product of, and follows from, the socio-economic and political practices of global market capitalism. Thus, Wood says, "The racial division of labor is reproduced with and without the aid of white racism" (74).

            The fundamental hiatus between the post- and pre-Evasion West is due to different conceptions of power attending the various stages of his writings. The post-Evasion conception is deeply indebted to poststructuralist and postmodernist conceptions of power as being both thoroughly nowhere and thus everywhere. Power is conceived in abstract and deeply non-pragmatic terms, despite being operative under the rubric of "prophetic pragmatism."

            This brings us to the question of what is continuous and indeed unites the early and later West. The brilliance of West's early work to advance a revolutionary African American Christianity, one that sought to synthesize Christianity and Marxism, is in its ability to uncover the ways in which class and capital structure relations so that they yield group coloring for their support, and to see how God-talk supports the social order of things. Marxism offered West a social theory able to demystify the operations of capital and, to an extent, of God-talk in stratifying groups according to class and then by race. The racial ordering of groups supports both intra- and inter-group class stratifications.

            Part of the demystifying work represented in West's call for a revolutionary African American Christianity, according to Wood, necessarily entails a critique, one inspired by Feuerbach as much as by Marx (can the two finally be separated?), of the ways in which Christianity itself camouflaged the operations of capital in the interests of those with and in power. In his use of Marxism as a social theory to accomplish what Christianity cannot, West resembles other liberationists like the Latin American theologians Gustavo Gutiérrez and Leonardo Boff and theologians in the Afro-Christian prophetic traditions like James H. Cone, Jacquelyn Grant, and Delores Williams. The fundamental assumption is that Christianity is not a social theory, and thus requires assistance to demythologize what it can only speak of in mythological terms.

            For West, however, a Christianity critiqued and humbled by a Marxist-inspired social theory does not mean the utter abandonment of Christianity. Indeed, Christianity is an essential and irreplaceable element in the Marxist-Christian synthesis. Its indispensability has to do with its "more profound interpretation of the human condition" (31). Christianity's understanding of the human condition, as articulated by West, tutors Marxism's unbridled optimism about the perfectibility of human nature. For West, immanent to Christianity is a dialectical, theological anthropology that posits human nature and history as both dignified and depraved. The dignity of human nature means that it is good and worthy of salvation by God. This is the ultimate destiny of humanity, namely, its redemption by God. But the realization of humanity's teleological destiny is withheld from and unknown to us. The depravity of human nature, which consists in the tragic, evil, and the absurd confronting us in the interim, is what remains.

            This, for Wood, is clearly a problem. West has only concealed and repressed the ultimate facts, that is, the social roots, of the human predicament. For in the face of the depravity of human nature, West finds it necessary to confront another crucial question: what inspires persistence in working for more democratic socio-political structures in the face of the evil, tragedy, and absurdity of human existence as witnessed in the imperfect human negations before us? West's answer, so Wood shows, betrays just how much of a metaphysical thinker he, despite his Marxist orientation, remains. Belief in and dependence on what West calls in Prophecy Deliverance!, "the almighty power of a transcendent God…that can sustain a sense of hope and rescue human beings from their plight" (30-31): this is West's answer. The theism and theological anthropology underwriting this response, its employment of such theological, literary, and existentialist categories as "evil," the "absurd," and the "tragic," function in the end to "essentialize or to use Marx's concept, fetishize and thereby mystify the social roots" of these categories, thereby "[encouraging] the acceptance of the existing order of things at least as much as they discourage it" (31-32).

            The pre-Evasion West, then, in the end remains a metaphysical and "pantheological" thinker, and thus, within the deep structure of his thought, there is a thoroughgoing continuity with his later cultural and prophetic pragmatism. Indeed, the "prophetic," that is, the theological moment of prophetic pragmatism provides the metaphysical justification or, rather, mystification, as Wood would have it, of the metaphysical conception of power as "pantheologically" nowhere and thus everywhere according to the "pragmatic" moment of the post-Evasion prophetic pragmatism.

            Hence theology still functions in West's thought, according to Wood, to obfuscate the operations of capital in the modern world. Wood points to the problems of theism and of theological anthropology in West's thought. On both fronts there is metaphysical thinking. Another problematic side to West's theological anthropology is the way in which theological language underwrites the cultural rhetoric of multiculturalism, and it emerges most clearly in how West maintains the Christian side of the synthesis between Marxism and Christianity.

            "Marxists," claims West, "have not adequately investigated the complexity of culture in general and religion in particular," and so "what is needed is a mode of Marxist practice that critically engages cultural forms as sometimes justifying the dominant social relations and at other times providing the raw material for building opposition to the status quo" (22-23). This move entails a fundamental re-reading of Marxism and thus also of the ways in which capital structures the world. Class relations, the possession of power within those relations, and finally how racism is produced by those relations are no longer the teleological horizon within which to understand the world. West also insists that an adequate account of what ails us requires an account of culture and multicultural différence and a belief that the radical egalitarianism at the heart of Christianity will moderate cultural difference for the final realization of all individuality. Belief in God gives hope in the face of the nihilism and imperfect human negations that persist in the interim before any teleological or redeeming consummation of human nature. A theory of multicultural différence proves crucial to West's re-reading of Marx and the evils of capitalism through Christianity. The harvest of this move emerges most fully in the post-Evasion pragmatism.

            What is Wood's own proposal for overcoming the problems in West's prophetic pragmatism, indeed, in the general approach West's project takes from its inception? Wood proposes a return to the Marxist commitments of the early West. However, to ensure that the problems bedeviling the pre-Evasion West do not return, the Christian part of the Christianity-Marxism synthesis must be further demystified. It is here that Wood follows an emerging trajectory of thinking in the field of black religious scholarship, a trajectory seen in a number of scholars who themselves have been influenced by the black theology of James H. Cone, but see a need to go beyond it. In going beyond it many have turned to Cornel West and the tradition of pragmatism in America, which is now being mediated through Charles H. Long of the Chicago School of the history of religions.

            The problem with prophetic pragmatism, according to Wood, is that, "like other theologies of liberation, [it] uses theological categories to represent the conflict between private control over labor and its fruits and the potential to create a society based on democratic control" (37, italics mine). The great challenge to all liberation theologies, including prophetic pragmatism, is "resisting the metaphysical temptation, the otherworldly seduction, to translate political problems into theological categories" such that the theological categories and what they signify are real (37). Prophetic pragmatism, like so many liberation theologies, has yielded to temptation and has been beguiled by the allure of theology, and has thus sinned, in the end, reneging on its commitment to address the pragmata of existence—the things themselves, one might say—by mystifying them. Following Long as a way to stay more thoroughly Marxist and thus more rigorously pragmatic, Wood proposes that the true goal of liberation theology is

to create a society in which the need for liberation theology would not exist….The essence of liberation theology can be realized only by negating the world that produces the need for a theology of liberation, and the world that produces this theology can be negated only by realizing the essence of liberation theology. Once realized, liberation theology loses its raison d'être. (37)     Thus, liberation theologians must not seek to "reproduce the fundamental assumptions that inform [traditional] Christian theology," given that those assumptions mask the roots of what socially and politically ail us (37).

            Wood's analysis raises a number of important questions; because of space constraints, I can only address what I perceive to be the most pressing. They concern, first, his reading of the fundamental problem of West's prophetic pragmatism, and second, his proposal for a return to a Marxist interpretation of power, but more rigorously executed to demystify God-talk and thereby to truly engage the pragmata of existence. Wood says of West that he has insufficiently demystified theological speech in his discourse by retaining its most problematic metaphysical moments. The retention of this mystifying moment creates the space for further mystifications around a cultural, indeed, a multicultural interpretation of race with its problematic, that is, Foucaultian, understanding of power. But is this really the problem with West's prophetic pragmatism, especially as it is rooted in his early programmatic calls for a radical African American Christianity? For what most afflicts West's work from its inception is its abstract, one could say, non-pragmatic, vision of Christian identity as not concretely embodied in the world. The problem I found in Locke's critical pragmatism applies as well to West's prophetic pragmatism. Abstracting African American Christianity leads West to negotiate a Marxist or Foucaultian vision of power for the interpretation of what besets the modern world on matters of race and beyond.

            But Wood's own proposal to make West more rigorously Marxist and pragmatic through an appropriation of insights from Charles H. Long gets us no further. For he too accepts West's fundamental bracketing of Christianity. For neither West nor Wood is Christianity a socially constituted, embodied, and therefore concrete mode of life, which encodes a form of socio-political existence that participates in the trinitarian dynamism through Jesus Christ. Having made this decision to bracket Christianity, it can never be asked: What conception of power inheres in Christian existence, and how does this mode of power exceed both Marxist and Foucaultian visions of power?

            Having raised these questions about Wood's reading of West, a final problem demands mention insofar as it is central to a consideration of pragmatism. Whatever incompatibilities there may be between Marxism and Christianity resulting from their respective "faith claims," as West calls them, there remains the question of whether supplanting capitalism with a Marxist-inspired economics and politics simply replaces one form of tyranny with another. Is it not the case that a Marxist-inspired economics, with attendant policies like the equitable redistribution of goods and so forth, is finally coercive? And is not coercion but another form of abstraction from the pragmata of existence? I do not raise these questions as an argument for the veracity of capitalism as such. Rather, I raise them to suggest that the turn to a wholesale Marxism is itself fraught with "un-pragmatic" difficulties. But I also raise the question to clear the way for a reconsideration of Christianity as, in its concreteness, already entailing a mode of existence that operates according to a politics and even economics of suffering charity. In such a politics, driven as it is by freedom, the incarnate God can actually accomplish the ends of Marxism non-coercively.



1 For a more detailed discussion of the modern construction of race, see my Race: A Theological Account, forthcoming from Oxford University Press.